Logical Fallacies
Logic is the study of reasoning -- the nature of
good (correct) reasoning and of bad (incorrect) reasoning. Its focus is
the method by which an argument unfolds, not whether any
arbitrary statement is true or accurate. Thus,
an argument can be both deductively valid and perfectly absurd, as in 1.
All telephone poles are elephants. 2. Sally is a telephone pole. 3.
Therefore, Sally is an elephant. The conclusion is valid because it
conforms to a correct syllogistic pattern -- in this case, affirmation of
the antecedent -- but is ludicrous at the same time. As a "branch" of philosophy, logic is often broken
down into many subsets: for instance, modal logic, many-valued logic,
modern logic, symbolic logic, formal and informal logic, deductive and
inductive logic. Those interested in pursuing the subject in depth should
read and carefully examine the long articles in The Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, especially "A Glossary of Logical Terms." Each article is
followed by an extensive bibliography. (See also Logic.) A fallacy is an invalid form of
argument, an instance of incorrect reasoning. Below is a list of common
fallacies. Hit the "Back" button to return to the top.
List of Fallacies:
affirming the consequent
anthrocentric fallacy
appeal to authority
a
priori fallacies
arguing
from "is" to "ought"
argumentum ad baculinum
argumentum ad captandum
argumentum
ad crumenam
argumentum ad hominem argumentum ad ignorantiam
argumentum
ad lazarum
argumentum ad misericordiam
argumentum ad populum
argumentum ad verecundiam (see
"appeal to authority") argumentum
ex silentio
begging the question
circular
reasoning
equivocation
fallacy of false alternatives
fallacies of interrogation
flamboyance
gadarene
swine fallacy
genetic fallacy
hasty generalization
if-then fallacies
ignoratio elenchi
invincible
ignorance
naturalistic fallacy
non sequitur
paralogism
performative
contradiction
petitio principii (see
"begging the question")
poisoning
the wells
post hoc ergo propter hoc
red herring
straw man fallacy
tu quoque fallacy
undistributed
middle
Further Investigation
affirming the consequent -- A fallacy of the form "if A, then B; B,
therefore A". Example: "If Smith testifies against Jones in court, Jones
will be found guilty. Jones was found guilty. Therefore, Smith must have
testified against him." {Jones could have been found guilty without
Smith's testimony.}
anthrocentric (human-centered) fallacy -- This one isn't found in standard texts, but was
described by John Stuart Mill in System of
Logic. Consider the example of a preacher who one day takes someone supposedly possessed of a demon,
throws his hand on her forehead, and shouts, "Get out! Leave this body!"
Even supposing that demons exist, one might find it curious that they
understand English, obey peremptory commands, and are easily
influenced by incantations and rituals. The a.f. here occurs at the
presupposition level: human language, reason, instincts, and desires are
assumed to be the orbit around which everything else in the universe
(including the aforementioned demons) revolve.
appeal to authority -- Known also as the argumentum ad
verecundiam fallacy. An appeal to authority is ordinarily one good way
to buttress a line of thought. The practice becomes fallacious
when one of the following happens: the authority is not an expert in the
field in which one is speaking; the allusion to authority masks the fact
that experts may be divided down the middle on the subject; no explicit
reference is made to the authority.
a
priori fallacies
-- From The Encyclopedia of Philosophy: "Under the heading of
a priori fallacies Mill listed a number of natural prejudices, including
the popular superstition that words have a magical power and such
philosophical dogmas as that which is true of our ideas of things must be
true of the things themselves; that differences in nature must correspond
to our received (linguistic) distinctions; that whatever is, is rationally
explicable; that there is no action at a distance; that every phenomenon
has a single cause; and that effects must resemble their causes. These are
all errors, but we can go further and recognize a general apriorist
fallacy, which consists in trying to base knowledge of fundamental
synthetic truths on anything other than empirical evidence."
arguing
from "is" to "ought"
-- A fallacy first articulated by David Hume (1711-1776) in which
someone argues from a premise containing only a descriptive term, to a
conclusion containing an "ought." Example: "There is
nothing morally wrong with the institution of slavery. It has been with us
in some form for thousands of years." (The fact that slavery has been
with us or is with us is not moral justification of the act. What is may
not be the same thing as what ought to be.)
argumentum
ad baculinum -- Fallacy that occurs when
threat of force is made, either implicitly or explicitly.
Example: "I'm willing to discuss this in even more depth, but if you don't
come around soon, there may be dire consequences."
(Baculum from the Latin means "stick".)
argumentum ad captandum -- Any specious or unsound argument that is likely to
win popular acceptance. (literally, "for catching the common
herd").
argumentum
ad crumenam --
The fallacy of supposing that a conclusion must be valid because the
person making the argument is wealthy. (Crumena from the Latin
means "purse".) An instance of this fallacy is when someone
turns to another and says, "Well, if you're so smart, why aren't you
rich?" One can be both smart and poor, as indeed
numerous philosophers throughout history were (e.g., Lao-Tzu, Socrates,
Spinoza).
argumentum ad hominem ("argument against the person") -- A common fallacy in which someone argues against a position or
claim by assailing the proponent of it. The truth or falsehood of a
position doesn't depend on who does (or doesn't) espouse it. e.g.
"You can't trust Jones' theory of electromagnetic particles because he's a
communist." (The theory is good or bad because it comports (or doesn't
comport) with certain facts and evidence, not because the man propounding
it holds a political affiliation.)
argumentum ad ignorantiam ("arguing from ignorance") -- A fallacy that occurs when someone argues that because we don't
know something is true, it must be false, or because we lack proof that a
statement is false, it must be true. Ignorance or lack of
evidence doesn't necessarily mean a position or claim is true or false.
Common Examples: "No one has ever proven that UFOs exist.
Therefore, they don't exist." (Something can exist despite the absence of
confirmation. Lack of proof is justification for caution or even
scepticism, but not dogmatic assertions.) "There is simply no proof
that God exists. Therefore, God doesn't exist." (God might exist even
though there is no way empirically to prove it.)
argumentum
ad lazarum --
The fallacy of supposing a conclusion is valid because the argument is
made by a poor person. It is the opposite of the ad crumenam
fallacy.
argumentum ad misericordiam -- Occurs when an appeal is made to
pity or to one's sympathetic nature. Example: "Augusto Pinochet is
an old, dying man. It is wrong to make him stand trial for alleged
offenses."
argumentum ad populum -- This fallacy occurs when
an argument panders to popular passion or sentiment. When, for instance, a
politician exclaims in a debate that his opponent "is out of step with the
beliefs of everyone in the audience," he/she is committing the fallacy.
The legitimacy of a statement depends not on its
popularity, but on its truth credentials.
argumentum
ex silentio
-- The fallacy of supposing that someone's silence is necessarily proof of
ignorance. Two people, for instance, may be debating a political issue on
a cable news program. One may be in the studio with the host, the other
appearing via satellite. Their time on air reaches the point when each
only has a few seconds left to make a closing comment. One of the debaters
asks his opponent a very technical, complex question, and the opponent is
speechless for a few seconds. "Go ahead," the debater screams.
"Answer my question! See? He can't answer." A viewer may be left
with the impression that the person's speechlessness is tantamount to
ignorance, when in fact any number of things could have happened: 1) the
satellite connection could've been lost or experiencing problems; 2) the
debater was thinking about how best to answer a difficult question under
such an immediate time constraint; 3) the debater might not have even
heard the whole question. There may be reasons for temporary silence other
than ignorance.
begging the question -- Circular reasoning in
which a claim is assumed to be true and is then tucked in the conclusion.
e.g. "Government by the people is ideal because democracy is the
least inadequate form of government." ("Government by the people" is the
working definition of democracy; the first part of the statement needs to
be proven, not reasserted in the predicate.)
circular
reasoning
-- Sometimes known as circulus in demonstrando, or begging the
question. H.W. Fowler, in Modern English Usage, puts it this way:
"The basing of two conclusions each upon the other. That the world is
good follows from the known goodness of God; that God is good is known
from the excellence of the world he has made."
equivocation -- Sometimes referred to as
"amphiboly". A fallacy that stems from the ambiguous meaning of certain
words. For example, 1. Only man is logical. 2. No woman is a man. 3.
Therefore, no woman is logical. "Man" in the first sentence really means
"mankind," "humankind," "homo sapiens". "Man" in the second sentence means
"maleness". The syllogism appears to be valid, but in fact is fallacious
because of the subtle shift in meaning.
fallacy of false
alternatives -- A fallacy occurring when the number of
alternatives is said to be fewer than the actual number. Common
examples of this fallacy are statements containing either/or, nothing/but,
all-or-nothing elements. Examples: "Is she a Democrat or a
Republican?" (She may be a socialist, a libertarian, a Leninist, an
anarchist, a feminist or any number of other things, including one who is
strictly apolitical.) "If you aren't for your country, then you are
against it." (One may be neither "for" nor "against" but may occupy a
position of strict neutrality or be affirmative sometimes and critical at
others.)
fallacies of interrogation -- There are two forms of
this particular fallacy. One is asking two or more questions and demanding
a single answer when, in fact, each question might require separate
treatment. The other form is asking a question whose answer would
necessitate acceptance of a presupposition, one which the answerer might
separately deny. The famous example of this second form is asking, "Do you
still beat your wife?" Answering "no" legitimates the question and does
nothing to contradict the presupposition that the husband once did beat
his wife. Asking a question with presuppositions is fine so long as a
narrow answer is not demanded.
flamboyance -- The manner in which someone speaks can
easily draw unwarranted support for a thesis or idea. Incisive wit, verbal
facility, equanimity and repartee have no bearing at
all on the soundness/legitimacy of a position. It is
the essence of what is said, not the manner in which
it is said, that counts. As Bertrand Russell once noted, the purpose of
being educated is to defend ourselves against the seductions of eloquence.
genetic fallacy -- A fallacy that occurs when someone attacks the
cause or origin of a belief rather than its substance. Why a person
believes something is not relevant to the belief's
legitimacy/soundness/validity. Example: "Smith's belief in God
stems from a subsconscious need for a fatherly figure and is thus a total
joke." (The psychological link may in fact be true and may even shed some
light on the personality of Smith, but is nevertheless irrelevant to the
truth/falsehood of his belief.)
hasty generalization -- The habit of arriving at a bold
conclusion based on a limited sample of evidence. This often occurs with
statistics. For instance, someone may ask ten women and one man what their
opinion is of contemporary male-female relationships and from this sample
draw a sweeping conclusion; hasty generalization would then be said to
exist.
if-then fallacies -- 1. Affirming the consequent (If P, then
Q. Q. Therefore P.). 2. Denying the antecedent (If P, then Q. Not
P. Therefore not Q.) 3. Converting a conditional (If P, then Q.
Therefore if Q, then P.) 4. Negating antecedent and consequent (If
P, then Q. Therefore if not P, then not Q.)
ignoratio elenchi ("ignoring of the
disproof") --
A fallacy that consists in disproving or proving something different from
what is in question or called for. It can also be called the
irrelevance fallacy. Example: "You cannot convict my
client of murder. We have proven that one of the arresting officers made
prejudicial remarks, remarks scornful of my client. Look at the videotape,
the audiotape, the man's own testimony. He is a full-blown racist; you
must not trust anything he says." (Undermining an allegation of murder is
something different than proving that one member of the plaintiff's team
is bigoted; hence, the i.e. fallacy here.)
invincible
ignorance
-- the fallacy of insisting on the legitimacy of one's position in the
face of contradictory facts. Statements like "I really don't care
what the experts say; no one is going to convince me that I'm wrong";
"nothing you say is going to change my mind"; "yeah, okay,
whatever!" are examples of this fallacy.
naturalistic
fallacy -- From the Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
"What G.E. Moore called the naturalistic fallacy is the identifying
of goodness with any natural characteristic, such as pleasantness or being
the object of desire. If there is a distinct property, goodness, it will
of course be an error to identify it with any other feature, even if the
two are coextensive, and this would be an example of the refusal to
distinguish what we cannot separate; however, it must first be shown that
there is such a property as Moore's goodness. Alternatively, if it is a
question of how the word 'good' is commonly used, then it would be an
error to say that it is used to convey some natural description. However,
if the naturalist is not trying to report the ordinary use, but is saying
that this ordinary use is somehow unsatisfactory (and also that there is
no such property as the one of which Moore speaks) and is therefore
proposing a different use, where is his mistake? It is true that if he
redefines 'good' as the name of some natural characteristic, but still
also uses the word in its ordinary evaluative or prescriptive sense, he
will be slipping into a fallacy of ambiguity; but a consistent ethical
naturalist may be committing no fallacy at all."
non
sequitur ("it does not follow") -- A
statement that does not logically follow from what preceded it; a
conclusion that does not follow from the premises.
paralogism -- Any fallacious
or illogical argument generally.
poisoning
the wells -- This entry comes from an article by Albury Castell
titled "Analyzing A Fallacy," which was included in the book Readings
In Speech, edited by Haig Bosmajian (Harper & Row, 1965). Here is
the full quote: "During the last century a famous controversy took
place between Charles Kingsley and Cardinal Newman. It began, I believe,
by Kingsley suggesting that truth did not possess the highest value for a
Roman Catholic priest; that some things were prized above truth. Newman
protested that such a remark made it impossible for an opponent to state
his case. How could Newman prove to Kingsley that he did have more regard
for truth than for anything else, if Kingsley argued from the premiss that
he did not? It is not merely a question of two persons entertaining
contradictory opinions. It is subtler than that. To put it baldly, Newman
would be logically 'hamstrung.' Any argument he might use to prove that he
did entertain a high regard for truth was automatically ruled out by
Kingsley's hypothesis that he did not. Newman coined the expression poisoning
the wells for such unfair tactics...The phrase poisoning the wells exactly
hits off the difficulty. If the well is poisoned, no water drawn from it
can be used. If a case is so stated that contrary evidence is
automatically precluded, no arguments against it can be used."
post hoc, ergo propter hoc ("after this, therefore because of
this") -- This might also be described as the causality fallacy: Event
Y follows from Event X, so one automatically concludes that
X caused Y. (A young man walks by a neighbor's house
and sees a cat scurrying away; he looks up and sees a giant hole in the
window. The hole, he infers, must have been caused by the cat, who fell
through the pane. The inference is hasty, because the hole might have been
caused by any number of things -- a baseball that missed a friend's glove
and flew over his head; young brothers fighting inside and accidentally
smashing the window, etc.).
red herring -- An attempt to divert attention from
the crux of an argument by introduction of anecdote, irrelevant detail,
subsidiary facts, tangential references, and the like.
straw man -- A fallacy that occurs when someone attacks a
less defensible position than the one actually being put forth. This
occurs very often in politics, when one seeks to derive maximum approval
for himself/herself or for a cause. Example: "Opposition to the
North American Free Trade Agreement amounts to nothing but opposition to
free trade." (Someone can believe in free and open trade and yet still
oppose NAFTA.)
tu quoque ("you too") fallacy -- The fallacy of assuming an
argument is specious because it is either inconsistent with the person's
actions or inconsistent with previous claims/arguments. A person may
"preach" about something and act in a very different manner, but this fact
has no bearing on the specific argument he is advancing at any time.
Inconsistency, moreover, may raise issues of hypocrisy or double
standards, but it does not bear upon the argument at hand. Example:
"Smith: If someone hits you, you should turn the
other cheek. Violence only begets violence, and violence in and of itself
is wrong. Jones: That's a joke. You used to hit people when they
picked a fight with you." (Smith may not have practiced what he now
preaches, but two of his premises -- that
violence only begets violence, and that violence is wrong -- need to be
carefully examined.)
undistributed
middle -- A fallacy of the form "All A are B. All C are B.
Therefore, all A are C." Consider: All elms are trees. All oaks are
trees. Therefore, all elms are oaks.
Further
Investigation
Years of intense study and training are not needed to develop a
rough understanding of logic or, for that matter, of any other branch
of philosophy. Much ground can be gained by reading a few chapters of
several books, by foraging through various collections in used or old
bookstores, and by visiting a few good sites on the web.
Below is a list of prominent logicians and their work:
Aristotle: Categories; On
Interpretation; Prior Analytics; Posterior Analytics;
Topics; Sophistical Refutations.
Francis
Bacon: Novum Organum
Descartes: Discourse on
Method
John Dewey: Reconstruction In
Philosophy
John Stuart Mill: System of
Logic
W.V. Quine,
Mathematical Logic.
Bertrand Russell: The Problems of
Philosophy; The Principles of Mathematics.
Gilbert Ryle: Dilemmas
Ludwig Wittgenstein: Philosophical
Investigations
Other
Works:
Rudolf Carnap,
Introduction to Symbolic Logic and its Applications.
Alonzo Church, Introduction
to Mathematical Logic.
M.R.
Cohen & Ernest Nagel, An Introduction to Logic and Scientific
Method.
W.W.
Fearnside & W.B. Holther, Fallacy -- The Counterfeit of Argument.
-
Return Home - |